Legal positivism

Doctrine (or set of doctrines) stemming primarily from English jurist John Austin (1790-1859) in his The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832).

It emphasizes what the law actually is rather than what it should be: it cannot, like natural law, be defined by reference to its content, but is what is commanded by the sovereign.

Source:
H L A Hart, The Concept of Law (1961); see especially p. 253

Importance

Seen by scholars as an important work[1][2] in understanding of a conceptual constructivist approach of the scientific way of thinking law in the new era of the jurisprudence of values, Bobbio’s book faces this challenge in eleven chapters.

Chapters

Part I

Introduction: natural law and positive law in thinking along the history

  1. Historical predecessors, relation between natural and positive law, the history context of the legal positivism, common law and civil law
  2. The historical law school as predecessor; Thibaut versus Savigny about the codification of law in Germany
  3. The Napoleonic Code in France; the exegesis school; Portalis
  4. The origins of legal positivism in Germany; Bentham and Austin; the illuminist inspiration; Jhering’s method of the juridical science

Part 2

Introduction: the main points of the juspositivism doctrine

  1. Positivism as non-value judgments; legal realism and legal positivism; formalism and legal positivism
  2. Definition of law as enforcement; Thomasius; Kant; JheringRoss
  3. Sources of law; judicial decisions as sources of law; equity; nature of things (Natur der Sache); uses and habits
  4. Imperative theory; AustinThon
  5. The theory of legal order
  6. The interpretation function of jurisprudence; integration and analogy
  7. Positivism as ideology; legal order as value of law[3]

Criticism

“The legal positivism considers only what is put by the State. Its basic thesis is that the law is product of human action and desire and no more of the divine natural or rational as affirmed formerly by the jusnaturalism. Various authors also defend that there isn’t necessarily a relation between law, moral and justice, because notions of justice and moral are time and space dependent and without political power to support them and impose them against who creates the juridical norms”[4]

Legal Positivism of Norberto Bobbio, shows us the final and most advanced reading of the legal positivism[5]

“Bobbio, about the first jusphilosophers of legal positivism, rhapsodizing a metaphor attributed to Newton, described himself as a dwarf on the shoulder of a giant, in the sense that ‘If we are on the shoulder of a giant, we can see more than even the giants themselves, but if there weren’t the giants, we couldn’t achieve that height'”.[1]

Bibliography

  • Bobbio, Norberto. Il Positivismo Giuridico, 3rd edition. Torino: G. Giapichelli, 1996, ISBN 8834861671

2 thoughts on “Legal positivism

  1. Hilde Vigo says:

    I simply could not leave your web site prior to suggesting that I really enjoyed the standard information a person provide for your visitors? Is gonna be back continuously to investigate cross-check new posts.

  2. zomenoferidov says:

    I’ve been absent for a while, but now I remember why I used to love this blog. Thank you, I will try and check back more frequently. How frequently you update your web site?

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *